Mind and creativity of hominins

ROBERT G. BEDNARIK

Robert G. Bednarik

In comparison to other disciplines, Pleistocene archaeology has an unusual capacity of getting it wrong most of the time: ever since the mid-19th century, when all archaeologists rejected the coexistence of humans and Pleistocene fauna (e.g. Boucher de Perthes 1846), every important innovation in this field has been universally rejected by all practitioners. This included, for example, the propositions introducing fossil man (Fuhlrott 1859), Palaeolithic ‘art’ (Sautuola 1880), Homo erectus (Dubois 1894) and australopithecines (Dart 1925); while the Piltdown fraud (Weiner et al. 1953) and the African Eve hoax (Bednarik 2008a), among hundreds of such examples, were readily accepted. This tendency of the discipline to be captivated by fads, but precipitously rejecting valid propositions continues to the present time, with such examples as the Flores “hobbit” case or the various controversies concerning rock art dating. Since many aspects of the most popular archaeology memes can safely be assumed to be still false, it would be only prudent to anticipate that the dominant notions about the minds of hominins or of the creativity of our ancestors might also be problematic.

Rather than succumbing to the inconsequential humanist concept of “mind” as referring to “conscious experience” and “intelligent thought” it may be more productive to consider the mind as a system of neural and endocrine processes, how they work, and how their interplay can be described. No entity definable as the human mind exists; like engrams (Lashley 1950), it has no dimensions, weight, appearance, composition or location; hence it has no neuroscientific existence. Similarly, the application of the humanist concept of creativity to the Pleistocene is fraught with difficulties. Ordinarily the term refers to invention or origination of any new thing that has value to society, but we possess no adequately secure knowledge about the circumstances of any innovation or perceived creation of the Pleistocene to justify a discourse on the origins of creativity. In short, before considering the workings of the hominin brain or its presumed reflections in the archaeological record we need to dispel the simplistic and ethnocentric popularisations archaeology has encouraged to arise.

A modern mind

The unscientific nature of most archaeological discourse is evident from, among other things, the misuse of concepts imported from scientific disciplines. For instance the biological concept of evolution perceives it as a purely dysteleological process, whereas archaeology applies teleologically guided assumptions of it to culture and technology, illustrating the incommensurability of scientific and archaeological epistemologies. Moreover, notions of cultural variables and their expressions are merely etic constructs or “observer-relative, institutional facts” (Searle 1995). All Pleistocene “cultures” are archaeofacts — invented entities based on perceived but etic implement types and their relative combinations within assemblages — yet it is obvious that tools do not define cultures. Variables such as palaeoart, which do present authentic cultural dimensions, have been forced into the imaginary schemes created, which are then attributed to a succession of human groups that never existed as identifiable ethnic, political, linguistic or cultural entities (such as “Mousterians”, “Aurignacians” or “Magdalenians”). More importantly, none of the dimensions relevant to the construct of “mind”, such as intellect, intention, motivation, cognition, meaning or behaviour is recoverable by archaeology, and they cannot be inferred from tools as implied by the underlying “lithocentric” mantra of the discipline.

With so many pivotal attributes of the unstable orthodoxies of Pleistocene archaeology being unreliable or ill-conceived it is not surprising that notions of hominin mind and creativity are just as specious. The dominant view, based on the now redundant replacement hypothesis (that a new species replaced all other humans), is that the “modern mind” can be traced back in the order of 30,000 years, to “anatomically modern humans”, being demonstrated especially by Aurignacian palaeoart. Most aspects of this belief are probably false: the earliest rock art and mobiliary art of that period are more likely in the order of 40,000 years old (Bednarik 2007; Sadier et al. 2012; Pike et al. 2012) and they are perhaps the work of robust Homo sapiens, such as the so-called Neanderthals (Bednarik 2007). Moreover, the naive assumption that these Aurignacians, quite apart from not being anatomically modern, thought in ways similar to present-day conspecifics can be shown to be false. All palaeoart was created by non-literate humans, whose brains functioned very differently from those of literate people (Helvenston 2013). In fact, it is only in recent historical times that we became modern (Latour 1993), and the imposition of modern, literate narratives on properties of incredibly remote societies needs to be questioned at every opportunity. Modern human behaviour is not only determined by the intrinsic neural structures and endocrine systems giving rise to it; these are demonstrably influenced by ontogenic experiences of the individual and their effects on these neural configurations. Cultural (i.e. learned) activity modifies both the chemistry and anatomy of the brain (Malafouris 2008), affecting the flow of neurotransmitters and hormones and the quantity of grey matter (Maguire et al. 2000; Draganski et al. 2004; Smail 2007). Even people of the Middle Ages existed in reality constructs profoundly differing from those of modern literate people, and we can be certain that these differences were far more pronounced in early Upper Palaeolithic times.

What is it that has convinced archaeologists that the Chauvet cave art, for instance, indicates the use of a modern mind? They believe to “communicate” with the palaeoartists (Mithen 1998) because they imagine being able to detect adequate clues in images to determine their meaning, hence it appears to them to have access to the “mind” of the artist. They cannot, however, tell us about the minds of their users, otherwise recent users of “Middle Palaeolithic” stone tools (e.g. Tasmanians) should also lack modern minds. Because they believe they detect interpretable details in images, they assume that these details must have been placed with the intention of rendering them interpretable by similar “minds”. In reality this “identification” process is a form of circular reasoning, reflecting the values, mental constructs and visual responses of the beholders rather than the producers of the rock art motifs. Given that the same interpreters would not assume to communicate with, say, a contemporary Aboriginal artist through his rock art, it would seem that this belief stems from the supposed (but unfalsifiable) naturalistic characteristics of the image. It has no scientific justification; it is a communication with the self.

Some commentators have taken the view that the “modern mind” postdates the early Upper Palaeolithic (e.g. Humphrey 1998 and debate therein), explicitly rejecting the opinion that neural modernity is indicated by iconographic depiction, or by any other archaeological indices of neural modernity in early societies. Other such cited indicators include projectile weapons, bladelets, bone artefacts, hafting, elaborate fire use, exploitation of marine resources and large game (e.g. Spikins 2009), which many archaeologists mistakenly believe to be Upper Palaeolithic innovations. Evidence of these advances can be found not only with Middle Palaeolithic/Middle Stone Age industries of the Old World, but also with Lower Palaeolithic/Early Stone Age technocomplexes. Indeed, if “mind” refers to the state and operation of the neural structures that are involved in moderating behavioural patterns, these must have been essentially modern at least since the end of the Early Pleistocene, i.e. for almost 800,000 rather than 30,000 years (Bednarik 2008a, 2011a). “Modern behaviour” does not refer to the behaviour of modern Westerners, or to that of any other extant human group. It is defined by the state of the neural structures that are involved in moderating behavioural patterns, which ultimately are determined by inhibitory and excitatory stimuli in the brain (Bednarik 2011b). So the question is: what types of evidence would suggest that these extant neural structures had been substantially established, and at what time does such evidence first occur?

If the above list of indicators were symptoms of mental modernity, it would clearly extend well into the Lower Palaeolithic, but there is no good reason to accept these archaeological propositions. Adaptive exploitation of marine resources is mastered by many species, and many carnivores kill prey that is larger than they are. Projectiles are used by various other primates, and hominids and later hominins seem to have used them throughout much of their existence. Elaborate fire use is first demonstrated at 1.7 million years ago (Beaumont 2011), while bladelets, bone artefacts and composite tools all occur later in the Lower Palaeolithic. They cannot, however, tell us about the minds of their users (consider Tasmanians with their “Middle Palaeolithic” technology). Theory of mind (ToM), level of consciousness and self-awareness would be more relevant, but are not considered because they cannot be excavated. Inferences derived from empirical archaeological knowledge are admitted selectively: if they reinforce the dominant model they are welcomed, if they contradict it they are eschewed (e.g. Rigaud 2006–2007; Rigaud et al. 2009). For instance language proficiency is crucial in forming human constructs of reality and cognitive dimensions (Bickerton 2010), and although palaeophysiology and linguistics (Falk 1975, 1983, 1987, 2009; Dunbar 2003) have, for very good reasons, long attributed language to most or all hominins, mainstream archaeology has in recent decades preferred to limit language ability to the progeny of an imaginary “African Eve” for which no credible evidence has ever been tendered. This extreme view illustrates the chasm between archaeology and science: it is biologically absurd that the enormous cost of encephalisation should not have involved significant evolutionary benefits. Given that natural selection can only select expressed characteristics, not latent ones, and that the human brain approached its modern size several hundreds of millennia ago, it needs to be explained what hominins did with these enlarged brains. Just as language can only be selected for after it has appeared (Bickerton 2010), so can larger brain size, and to imply, as archaeological interpretation does, that for millions of years this brain increased relentlessly without being much used is biologically incongruous. It is, nevertheless, the de-facto null hypothesis of Pleistocene archaeology, whereas science would tend to assume that the cost of encephalisation demands significant benefits.

ToM and self-awareness

Figure 1. Middle Acheulian proto-figurine from Tan-Tan, southern Morocco, with artificial grooves and traces of haematite coating.

The cognitive “explosion” or “great leap” around 40,000 years ago postulated by mainstream archaeology (Cann et al. 1987; Stringer and Andrews 1988) not only lacks a logical basis; it is contradicted even by the archaeological record. The preferred indicators that today’s human brain possesses the kind of structures that underwrite “modern” behavior and cognition are exograms, signs that humans are capable of storing symbolic information outside their brains. Middle Pleistocene (Lower Palaeolithic) examples of exograms have been classified into beads, petroglyphs, portable engravings, proto-sculptures (Figure 1), pigments and manuports (Bednarik 1992, 2003a). Although communication is possible by various means, it seems unlikely that maritime colonisation almost a million years ago was achievable without an appropriate form of “reflective” and perhaps recursive language (Bednarik 1999, 2003b). This provides an important anchor point for a realistic timeline of developing human competence in volitionally driven behavior, one of the quintessential aspects of humanness (Bednarik 2011b, 2012). Modernity in human behavior had begun, in the sense that the same neural structures and processes that determine this quality today were essentially in place. If this occurred around a million years ago, as appears to be the case, then the archaeological beliefs are false. If, on the other hand, only fully modern behavior qualifies for modernity, then it arose only in the most recent centuries, and it does not apply to extant illiterates or to traditional societies. It then becomes such a narrow definition that it is useless as a marker of human development. Either way orthodox archaeology misunderstood the advent of the “modern mind”.

Figure 2. Inter-connectivity as shown by brain signals traffic along white matter fibres in the left hemisphere, recorded by diffusion magnetic resonance imaging (MGH-UCLA Human Connectome Project).

Homology can provide some preliminary indications from reviewing empirically demonstrated ontogenic development. Intentional behavior can be detected by infants 5–9 months old (Woodward 1999), while at 15 months they can classify actions according to their goals (Csibra et al. 2003). The same abilities are available to chimpanzees and orang-utans (Call and Tomasello 1998), but apparently not to monkeys (Jellema et al. 2000). Between 18 and 24 months, the child establishes joint attention (Franco and Butterworth 1996), as well as engages in pretend-play, and it develops an ability to understand desires (Wellman and Wooley 1990; Rapacholi and Gopnik 1997; Wellman and Liu 2004). Again, apes use gaze monitoring to detect joint attention (Hare et al. 2000), but monkeys apparently do not. It is roughly at the age of forty months that the human child surpasses the ToM (theory of mind) level of the great apes (Bednarik 2012, 2013). Thus the executive control over cognition unique to humans, together with metarepresentation (Dennett 2000) and recursion, would be expected to have developed during the last 5 or 6 million years. Although the brain areas accounting for the latter two faculties remain unidentified, executive control resides in the frontal lobes. Since the frontal and temporal areas have experienced the greatest degree of enlargement in humans (Semendeferi et al. 2001; Bednarik and Helvenston 2012), the faculties facilitating uniquely human abilities would be expected to be most likely found there — although inter-connectivity (Figure 2) rather than discrete loci may have been the main driving force of cognitive evolution. It is precisely the expansion of association cortices that has made the human brain disproportionately large (Preuss 2000). It is with the appearance of “metarepresentation”, a representation (Von Eckardt 1999) of a representation (Leslie 1994; Baron-Cohen 1995; Dennett 2000; Perner and Garnham 2001), and with recursion that developed human ToM emerges, as these are lacking in the great apes (Suddendorf 1999; Call and Tomasello 1999). Similarly, the apes have so far provided no evidence of episodic memory or future planning (Suddendorf and Busby 2003). Episodic memory, which is identified with autonoetic consciousness, can be impaired in humans, e.g. in amnesia, Asperger’s syndrome, or in older adults (Gardiner 2001). It can be attributed to differential activity in the medial prefrontal and medial parietal cortices, imaging studies of episodic retrieval have shown (Lou et al. 2004).

Figure 3. The jaspilite or jasperite cobble deposited in Makapansgat Cave, South Africa, in an australopithecine-bearing sediment, suggesting that these Pliocene hominids (or contemporary hominins) recognised its remarkable natural features.

These homological considerations provided by primatology thus suggest that distinctive precursors of modernity in human behaviour, in the forms of ToM, consciousness and self-awareness, must have been present several million years ago; they can be assumed to have become gradually more established since then (Bednarik 2011a). By the beginning of the Middle Pleistocene, 780,000 years ago, modern human behaviour as a neurological and endocrine process must have been well established, in the sense that the structures involved in moderating behavioural patterns were substantially in place. For instance the earliest evidence of maritime colonisation, from about that time (Bednarik 1999, 2003b), demands that Homo erectus then possessed relatively complex communication, presumably in the form of speech. It also implies a variety of technological capacities, such as the use of cordage and knotting (Warner and Bednarik 1996). The neural structures underwriting human behaviour at that time should be visualised as being not significantly different from those of present-day humans of, say, 8–12 years of age that have not been modified by the use of written communication or other forms of exograms (extra-cortical memory records of ideas).

Exograms

Figure 4. Representative selection from hundreds of Acheulian stone beads which are rejected by replacement archaeologists because such objects are as impossible to them from that period as cave art of the Upper Palaeolithic once was to their equally obstinate predecessors of yesteryear .

There is no evidence that any extant non-human primate uses, let alone creates, exograms under natural conditions. The symbol systems used by primatologists to communicate with apes are all humanly created, and the question arises whether such symbols could be defined as exograms. This issue appears to help define them, because the use of externally stored memory presupposes the creation of exograms. Therefore the language boards and other communication devices of primatologists may define the difference between symbols and exograms: clearly they use referrers, but they do not constitute native or naturalised systems of external storage. On the other hand, exograms may not necessarily have referents, as they refer more typically to purely abstract concepts, whereas symbols by definition stand for other entities. Moreover, most symbols are shared with conspecifics, generally via culture, whereas there is a distinctive separation of personal exograms (not shared with conspecifics) and shared exograms (culturally determined).

Figure 5. Pendant of a perforated wolf’s tooth from Repolust Cave, Lower Palaeolithic, Austria.

The concept of external engrams (Lashley 1950) was first applied to non-figurative cave art (Bednarik 1987), before the neologism “exogram” was invented to name them (Donald 2001). Since certain forms in which they occur are readily identifiable on the archaeological record they provide the most comprehensive indices in estimating the cognitive complexity of hominins, but they can also demonstrate the inadequacies of archaeological inferences. For instance it is clear that the faculty of self-awareness in a social animal would logically lead to strategies of consciously expressing individualism. Most such evidence is of a nature possessing very low taphonomic thresholds (Bednarik 1994; but see McGrew and Marchant 1998; McGrew 2004 for apparent “self-decoration” of a chimpanzee), but beads and pendants are notable exceptions (Bednarik 1997, 2005, 2008b) providing glimpses of self-adornment. The several species indicating degrees of self-awareness (De Veer and Van Den Bos 1999; Gallup 1970, 1998; Gallup et al. 2002; Heyes 1998; Keenan et al. 2003; Mitchell 1993, 1997, 2002) are much the same as those shown to possess von Economo neurons (Seeley et al. 2006; Butti et al. 2009; Hakeem et al. 2009). The latter seem to occur in relatively large species with large brains and extensive social networks (Bednarik 2011b), and it may be that constructs of individuality evolved in tandem with these networks. It is difficult to see how social complexity could have developed beyond that of social insects without some level of self-awareness, just as the advent of self-awareness is hard to account for. Since self-awareness can safely be assumed to have been present in all hominin species, it helps account for the earliest known find implying recognition of iconic resemblance, the Makapansgat cobble (Bednarik 1998). Clearly, the pareidolic detection of human features presupposes apperceptive capability, in this instance some 2.4 to 2.9 million years ago (Figure 3). The lack of subsequent, more direct indications of self-awareness for much of the remaining history of hominins is apparent, but in view of the generic coarse resolution of the available record as well as the relevant taphonomy (not to mention archaeological neglect of such evidence) it is to be expected. Nevertheless, considering that from a biological perspective, items of self-adornment should appear early in the Pleistocene (Figure 4), it is rather surprising that they emerge only much later on the available record (Bednarik 1997, 2005, 2008b). And as with any material evidence contradicting their dogmas over the past couple of centuries, archaeologists have here also engaged in their standard response of explaining it away (d’Errico and Villa 1997; Rigaud 2006–2007; Rigaud et al. 2009). Numerous examples of this practice include d’Errico’s rejection of the Repolust Cave pendants (Figure 5), the Divje babe I bone flute (d’Errico et al. 1998) or the Berekhat Ram proto-figurine (Figure 6), although upon examination he did concede his error concerning the latter item (d’Errico and Nowell 2000). It is this consistent pattern of premature dismissal or misinterpretation of the most important finds of the time in question, in terms of their explanatory power, that detracts greatly from the value of the discipline.

Conclusion

Figure 6. Late Acheulian proto-figurine from Berekhat Ram, Israel.

The incommensurability of the biosciences and archaeology renders it inevitable that the minimalist explanations archaeology favours contradict the scientific perspective. According to Pleistocene archaeology, hominins prior to 40,000 years ago lacked symboling abilities and probably had no language. This is neuroscientifically incongruous and highly unlikely, given the numerous pelagic colonisations of the second half of the Pleistocene. It would imply that the millions of years of continuous encephalisation would have had severely limited cognitive effects. Yet archaeology’s “big bang of consciousness” (Klein and Edgar 2002) is supposed to have occurred at the very same time as the significant reduction of brain volume (by about 13%) within an instant in evolutionary time commenced (Bednarik 2014). This “creative explosion” (Pfeiffer 1983; Mithen 1998) is perceived at the beginning of a hypothetical period called the Upper Paleolithic, triggering a veritable quantum jump in cognitive and intellectual prowess. This myth attributing the advent of human modernity to the beginning of the Upper Palaeolithic and the arrival of supposedly anatomically modern humans is contradicted by virtually millions of exograms preceding these events either chronologically or technologically. For instance all of Australia’s Pleistocene petroglyphs relate to Middle rather than Upper Palaeolithic technologies (Figure 7), and all the world’s palaeoart exceeding 40,000 years in age (Bednarik 1992, 2003a; Beaumont and Bednarik 2013) refutes both the “explosion” and the replacement hypothesis it is tied to. The same can be said about evidence of presumed symbolic behaviour, be it the use of pigment (Beaumont and Bednarik 2012), of raptors’ feathers (Finlayson et al. 2012) and musical instruments (Turk and Dimkaroski 2011), or the language skills demonstrated by maritime colonisation skills (Bednarik 1999, 2003b). With its accommodative reasoning, intended to preserve the dogma, mainstream archaeology has rejected thousands of early manifestations of human “creativity”, and is therefore not in a good position to comment constructively on this topic. Moreover, creativity is no more archaeologically recoverable than intention, meaning or behaviour. This subject is therefore best left to the neurosciences (Bednarik 2011a, 2011b, 2012, 2013, 2016; Helvenston 2013; Dielenberg 2013).

Figure 7. Pleistocene petroglyphs, Sacred Canyon, South Australia.

Similarly, Pleistocene archaeology has consistently failed to provide a credible explanation for the origins of what it calls the human mind, or to even come close to locating its advent temporally or spatially. In fact it has consistently scorned or explained away all material finds that might illuminate the issue, and has substituted technological variables for cultural — even using them to deduce cognitive ability. Having failed to define cultures correctly it is in no position to judge the variables the neuro- or cognitive sciences need to engage with in clarifying these issues.

In the final analysis one has two choices in exploring questions of the origin of the human “mind” and “creativity”. One can admit archaeology’s fantasies, tainted by dogma as they are (especially the replacement hypothesis); or one can choose the more prudent path of science. The first approach places as much distance as possible between modern people and their hominin ancestors, and resists any suggestion of hominin sophistication. It also perceives isolated human populations that were engaged in frequent migrations across largely empty landscapes, a scenario that is evidently false as hominins occupied every possible niche in the course of the Middle Pleistocene, even the Arctic (at least in Finland and Russia). The second approach, via science, has had very limited attention, and can only offer preliminary findings at this stage. It sees genes and memes travelling by introgression through largely contiguous populations that had progressively occupied new geographical regions. But more relevantly, it starts with the null hypotheses that brain expansion is very expensive and would not have occurred if there were no commensurate benefits involved. Therefore a complexity of hominin cognition roughly proportionate to brain size is to be expected, and the “creative explosion” derives from an archaeological misconception. Since ToM, self-awareness and consciousness were certainly available to all human species, archaeology’s minimalist explanations contesting the evidence of hominin cognitive capabilities are incompatible with the most parsimonious null hypothesis of science.

 

Note: This is an updated and modified version of a paper published in 2015 in The Genesis of Creativity and the Origin of the Human Mind, edited by Barbora Půtová, Department of Culturology, The Faculty of Arts, Charles University in Prague.

 

REFERENCES

Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness: an essay of autism and theory of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Beaumont, P. B. 2011. The edge: more on fire-making by about 1.7 million years ago at Wonderwerk Cave in South Africa. Current Anthropology 52: 585–595.

Beaumont, P. B. and R. G. Bednarik 2012. A brief overview of major Pleistocene palaeoart sites in sub-Saharan Africa. In J. Clottes (ed.), L’art pléistocène dans de monde, Actes du Congrès IFRAO, Tarascon-sur-Ariège, septembre 2010, Special issue, Préhistoire, Art et Sociétés, Bulletin de la Société Préhistorique Ariège-Pyrénées LXV–LXVI: 92–93.

Beaumont, P. B. and R. G. Bednarik 2013. Tracing the emergence of palaeoart in sub-Saharan Africa. Rock Art Research 30(1): 33–54.

Bednarik, R. G. 1987. Engramme und Phosphene. Zeitschrift für Ethnologie 112(2): 223–235.

Bednarik, R. G. 1992. Palaeoart and archaeological myths. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 2(1): 27–43.

Bednarik, R. G. 1994. A taphonomy of palaeoart. Antiquity 68(258): 68–74.

Bednarik, R. G. 1997. The role of Pleistocene beads in documenting hominid cognition. Rock Art Research 14(1): 27–41.

Bednarik, R. G. 1998. The ‘australopithecine’ cobble from Makapansgat, South Africa. South African Archaeological Bulletin 53: 4–8.

Bednarik, R. G. 1999. Maritime navigation in the Lower and Middle Palaeolithic. Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences Paris, Earth and Planetary Sciences 328: 559–563.

Bednarik, R. G. 2003a. The earliest evidence of palaeoart. Rock Art Research 20(1): 89–135.

Bednarik, R. G. 2003b. Seafaring in the Pleistocene. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 13(1): 41–66.

Bednarik, R. G. 2005. Middle Pleistocene beads and symbolism. Anthropos 100(2): 537–552.

Bednarik, R. G. 2007. Antiquity and authorship of the Chauvet rock art. Rock Art Research 24(1): 21–34.

Bednarik, R. G. 2008a. The mythical Moderns. Journal of World Prehistory 21(2): 85–102.

Bednarik, R. G. 2008b. Beads and the origins of symbolism. Time and Mind: The Journal of Archaeology, Consciousness and Culture 1(3): 285–318.

Bednarik, R. G. 2011a. The human condition. Springer, New York.

Bednarik, R. G. 2011b. The origins of human modernity. Humanities 1(1): 1–53; doi:10.3390/h1010001; http://www.mdpi.com/2076-0787/1/1/1/.

Bednarik, R. G. 2012. An aetiology of hominin behaviour. HOMO — Journal of Comparative Human Biology 63: 319–335.

Bednarik, R. G. 2013. The origins of modern human behavior. In R. G. Bednarik (ed.), The psychology of human behaviour, pp. 158. Nova Science Publishers, New York.

Bednarik, R. G. 2014. Doing with less: hominin brain atrophy. HOMO — Journal of Comparative Human Biology 65: 433–449.

Bednarik, R. G. 2016. An etiology of human behavior. In R. G. Bednarik (ed.), Understanding human behavior: theories, patterns and developments, pp. 6393. Nova Science Publishers, New York.

Bednarik, R. G. and P. A. Helvenston 2012. The nexus between neurodegeneration and advanced cognitive abilities. Anthropos 107(2): 511–527.

Bickerton, D. 2010. Adam’s tongue: how humans made language, how language made humans. Hill and Wang, New York,

Boucher de Perthes, J. 1846. Antiquités celtiques et antédiluviennes. Treuttel et Wurtz, Paris.

Butti, C., C. C. Sherwood, A. Y. Hakeem and J. M. Allman 2009. Total number and volume of von Economo neurons in the cerebral cortex of cetaceans. Journal of Comparative Neurology 515(2): 243–259.

Call, J. and M. Tomasello 1998. Distinguishing intentional from accidental actions in orangutans (Pongo pygmaeus), chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes), and human children (Homo sapiens). Journal of Comparative Psychology 112(2): 192–206.

Call, J. and M. Tomasello 1999. A nonverbal false belief task: the performance of children and great apes. Child Development 70(2): 381–395.

Cann, R. L., M. Stoneking and A. C. Wilson 1987. Mitochondrial DNA and human evolution. Nature 325: 31–36.

Csibra, G., S. Biro, O. Koos and G. Gergely 2003. One-year-old infants use teleological representations of actions productively. Cognitive Science 27(1): 111–133.

Dart, R. A. 1925. Australopithecus africanus: the man-ape of South Africa. Nature 115: 195–199.

Dennett, D. 2000. Making tools for thinking. In D. Sperber (ed.), Metarepresentations: a multidisciplinary perspective, pp. 17–29. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

d’Errico, F. and A. Nowell 2000. A new look at the Berekhat Ram figurine: implications for the origins of symbolism. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 10(1): 123–167.

d’Errico, F. and P. Villa 1997. Holes and grooves: the contribution of microscopy and taphonomy to the problem of art origins. Journal of Human Evolution 33: 1–31.

d’Errico, F., P. Villa, A. C. Pinto Llona and R. R. Idarraga 1998. A Middle Palaeolithic origin of music? Using cave-bear bone accumulations to assess the Divje babe I bone ‘flute’. Antiquity 72: 65–79.

De Veer, M. W. and R. Van Den Bos 1999. A critical review of methodology and interpretation of mirror self-recognition research in nonhuman primates. Animal Behavior 58: 459–468.

Dielenberg, R. A. 2013. The comparative psychology of human uniqueness: a cognitive behavioral review. In R. G. Bednarik (ed.), The psychology of human behaviour, pp. 111182. Nova Science Publishers, New York.

Donald, M. 2001. A mind so rare: the evolution of human consciousness. W.W. Norton, New York.

Draganski, B., C. Gaser, V. Bush, G. Schuierer, U. Bogdahn and A. May 2004. Changes in grey matter induced by training. Nature 427(6972): 311–312.

Dubois, E. 1894. Pithecanthropus erectus, eine menschenähnliche Übergangsform aus Java. Landersdrucherei, Batavia.

Dunbar, R. 2003. The social brain: mind, language, and society in evolutionary perspective. Annual Review of Anthropology 32: 163–181.

Falk, D. 1975. Comparative anatomy of the larynx in man and chimpanzee: implications for language in Neanderthal. American Journal of Physical Anthropology 43: 123–132.

Falk, D. 1983. Cerebral cortices of east African early hominids. Science 221: 1072–1074.

Falk, D. 1987. Hominid paleoneurology. Annual Review of Anthropology 16: 13–30.

Falk, D. 2009. Finding our tongues: mothers, infants and the origins of language. Basic Books, New York.

Finlayson, C., K. Brown, R. Blasco, J. Rosell, J. J. Negro, G. R. Bortolotti, G. Finlayson, A. S. Marco, F. G. Pacheco, J. R. Vidal, J. S. Carrión, D. A. Fa and J. M. R. Llanes 2012. Birds of a feather: Neanderthal exploitation of raptors and corvids. Plus One 7(9); www.plosone.org.

Franco, F. and G. Butterworth 1996. Pointing and social awareness: declaring and requesting in the second year. Journal of Child Language 23(2): 307–336.

Fuhlrott, C. J. 1859. Menschliche Überreste aus einer Felsengrotte des Düsselthals. Ein Beitrag zur Frage über die Existenz fossiler Menschen. Verhandlungen des Naturhistorischen Vereins Preussen und Rheinland Westphalen 16: 131–153.

Gallup, G. G., Jr. 1970. Chimpanzees: self recognition. Science 167(3914): 86–87.

Gallup, G. G., Jr. 1998. Self-awareness and the evolution of social intelligence. Behavioral Processes 42: 239–247.

Gallup, G. G., Jr., J. L. Anderson and D. P. Shillito 2002. The mirror test. In M. Bekoff, C. Allen and G. M. Burghardt (eds), The cognitive animal: empirical and theoretical perspectives on animal cognition, pp. 325–333. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

Gardiner, J. M. 2001. Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness: a first-person approach. Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences 356(1413): 1351–1361.

Hakeem, A. Y., C. C. Sherwood, C. J. Bonar, C. Butti, P. R. Hof and J. M. Allman 2009. Von Economo neurons in the elephant brain. Anatomical Record 292(2): 242–248.

Hare, B., J. Call, B. Agnetta and M. Tomaselli 2000. Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour 59: 771–785.

Helvenston, P. A. 2013. Differences between oral and literate cultures: what we can know about Upper Paleolithic minds. In R. G. Bednarik (ed.), The psychology of human behavior, pp. 59–110. Nova Science Publishers, New York.

Heyes, C. M. 1998. Theory of mind in nonhuman primates. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21(1): 101–134.

Humphrey, N. 1998. Cave art, autism, and the evolution of the human mind. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 8(2): 165–191.

Jellema, T., C. I. Baker, B. Wicker and D. I. Perrett 2000. Neural representation for the perception of the intentionality of actions. Brain and Cognition (Special Issue: Cognitive Neuroscience of Actions) 44(2): 280302.

Keenan, J. P., D. Falk and G. C. Gallup 2003. The face in the mirror: the search for the origins of consciousness. Harper Collins Publishers, New York.

Klein, R. G. and B. Edgar 2002. The dawn of human culture: a bold new theory on what sparked the ‘big bang’ of human consciousness. Wiley & Sons, New York.

Lashley, K. 1950. In search of the engram. Society of Experimental Biology Symposium 4: 454–482.

Latour, B. 1993. We have never been modern. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

Leslie, A. M. 1994. Pretending and believing: issues in the theory of ToMM. Cognition 50: 211–238.

Lou, H. C., B. Luber, M. Crupain, J. P. Keenan, M. Nowak, T. W. Kjaer, H. A. Sackeim and S. H. Lisanby 2004. Parietal cortex and representation of the mental self. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, U.S.A. 101(17): 6827–6832.

Maguire, E. A., D. G. Gadian, I. S. Johnsrude, C. D. Good, J. Ashburner, R. S. J. Frackowiak and C. D. Frith 2000. Navigation-related structural change in the hippocampi of taxi drivers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, U.S.A. 97(8): 4398–4403.

Malafouris, L. 2008. Beads for a plastic mind: the ‘blind man stick’ (BMS) hypothesis and the active nature of material culture. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 18(3): 401–414.

McGrew, W. C. 2004. The cultured chimpanzee. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

McGrew, W. C. and L. F. Marchant 1998. Chimpanzee wears a knotted skin ‘necklace’. Pan African News 5(1): 8–9.

Mitchell, R. W. 1993. Mental models of mirror-self-recognition: two theories. New Ideas in Psychology 11: 295–325.

Mitchell, R. W. 1997. Kinesthetic-visual matching and the self-concept as explanations of mirror-self-recognition. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 27: 18–39.

Mitchell, R. W. 2002. Subjectivity and self-recognition in animals. In M. R. Leary and J. P. Tangney (eds), Handbook of self and identity, pp. 567–595. Guilford Press, New York.

Mithen, S. (ed.) 1998. Creativity in human evolution and prehistory. Routledge, New York.

Perner, J. and W. A. Garnham 2001. Actions really do speak louder than words — but only implicitly. Young children’s understanding of false belief in action. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 19(3): 413–432.

Pfeiffer, J. E. 1983. The creative explosion: an inquiry into the origins of art and religion. Harper & Row, New York.

Pike, A. W. G., D. L. Hoffmann, M. García-Diez, P. B. Pettitt, J. Alcolea, R. De Balbin, C. González-Sainz, C. de las Heras, J. A. Lasheras, R. Montes and J. Zilhão 2012. U-series dating of Paleolithic art in 11 caves in Spain. Science 336: 1409–1413.

Preuss, T. M. 2000. What’s human about the human brain. In M. S. Gazzaniga (ed.), The new cognitive neurosciences, pp. 1219–1234. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Rapacholi, B. M. and A. Gopnik 1997. Early reasoning about desires. Evidence from 14- and 18-months-olds. Developmental Psychology 33(1): 12–21.

Rigaud, S. 2006–2007. Révision critique des Porosphaera globularis interprétées comme éléments de parure acheuléens. Unpubl. MA thesis, Université Bordeaux 1.

Rigaud, S., F. d’Errico, M. Vanhaeren and C. Neumann 2009. Critical reassessment of putative Acheulean Prosphaere globularis beads. Journal of Archaeological Science 36: 25–34.

Sadier, B., J.-J. Delannoy, L. Benedetti, D. L. Bourlès, S. Jaillet, J.-M. Geneste, A.-E. Lebatard and M. Arnold 2012. Further constraints on the Chauvet Cave artwork elaboration. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciencees, U.S.A. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1118593109.

Sautuola, M. Sanz de 1880. Breves appuntes sobre algunos obietos prehistóricos de la Provincia de Santander. Martínez, Santander.

Searle, J. R. 1995. The construction of social reality. Allen Lane, London.

Seeley, W. W., D. A. Carlin and J. M. Allman 2006. Early frontotemporal dementia targets neurons unique to apes and humans. Annals of Neurology 60(6): 660–667.

Semendeferi, K., E. Armstrong, A. Schleicher, K. Zilles and G. W. Van Hoesen 2001. Prefrontal cortex in humans and apes: a comparative study of area 10. American Journal of Physical Anthropology 114(3): 224–241.

Smail, L. M. 2007. On deep history and the brain. University of California Press, Berkeley.

Spikins, P. 2009. Autism, the integrations of ‘difference’ and the origins of modern human behaviour. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 19(2): 179–201.

Stringer, C. B. and P. Andrews 1988. Genetic and fossil evidence for the origin of modern humans. Science 239: 1263–1268.

Suddendorf, T. 1999. The rise of the metamind. In M. C. Corballis and S. Lea (eds), The descent of mind: psychological perception on hominid evolution (pp. 218260). Oxford University Press, London.

Suddendorf, T. and J. Busby 2003. Mental time travel in animals? Trends in the Cognitive Sciences 7: 391–396.

Turk, M. and L. Dimkaroski 2011. Neanderthal flute from Divje babe I: old and new findings. In B. Toškan (ed.), Fragments of Ice Age environments. Proceedings in honour of Ivan Turk’s jubilee, pp. 251265. Ljubljana.

Von Eckardt, B. 1999. Mental representation. In R. A. Wilson and F. C. Keil (eds), The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences, pp. 527529. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Warner, C. and R. G. Bednarik 1996. Pleistocene knotting. In J. C. Turner and P. van de Griend (eds), History and science of knots, pp. 3–18. World Scientific, Singapore.

Weiner, W. S., K. P. Oakley and W. E. Le Gros Clark 1953. The solution of the Piltdown problem. Bulletin of the British Museum (Natural History) Geology 2(3): 141–146.

Wellman, H. and D. Liu 2004. Scaling theory of mind tasks. Child Development 75(2): 523–541.

Wellman, H. and J. Wooley 1990. From simple desires to ordinary beliefs: the early development of everyday psychology. Cognition 35(3): 245–275.

Woodward, A. 1999. Infants’ ability to distinguish between purposeful and non-purposeful behaviors. Infant Behavior Development 22(2): 145–160.

 

 

Be the first to comment

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published.


*


This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.